Skip to main content

Is science or history better?


The following essay is my response to the International Baccalaureate's Theory of Knowledge question title option for 2021-2022: "Is there solid justification for regarding knowledge in the natural sciences more highly than another area of knowledge? Discuss with reference to the natural sciences and one other area of knowledge." I chose history as the additional area of knowledge, as there is often debate concerning whether science or history is more important. All rights go to IB for this prompt and the subsequent triggering of my thoughts and opinion.

-

Is there solid justification for regarding knowledge in the natural sciences more highly than another area of knowledge? Discuss with reference to the natural sciences and one other area of knowledge.

It was the intellectual Arthur Schlesinger Jr. who once declared that “science and technology revolutionize our lives, but memory, tradition and myth frame our response.” He compares two areas of human knowledge that shape who we are and model our future – the natural sciences and history. This essay is hence aimed to discuss the justification of the former area of knowledge as being regarded more highly than the latter. Justification is an essential quality of a knowledge that is defined as a justified true belief; the act of solidly justifying involves reasoning for an argument that is well-founded. Moreover, when one regards a certain knowledge “more highly” than another, one underlines a value that is derived from the certainty, accuracy, as well as usefulness of that certain knowledge. Value in natural science stems from the reliability in its empirical methodology as well as from its ability to solve tomorrow’s problems. In history, the fact that knowledge is created through the interpretation of the past cultivates uncertainty and misunderstandings, consequently undermining its value. Thus, knowledge in the natural sciences may be regarded more highly than that of history due to its greater accuracy, implications, as well as relevance to the modern world.

First, concerning the natural sciences, there is indeed solid justification for regarding knowledge in this area more highly than that in history, because of its increased reliability and bearing to our world. Generally, scientific theory is developed and validated by using empirical methods, which necessitate the direct and present observation of real life. Specifically, through inductive and deductive reasoning, the scientist makes broad generalizations from specific observations, and then utilizes this to forecast specific and defined results. Scientific knowledge therefore stems from unequivocal and upfront evidence. The empirical methodology of science also requires peer review, in which people collaborate and check one another’s ideas to expand knowledge. This essential aspect of the scientific method, aimed to limit any ambiguity within the scientific community, is underlined in essence by prominent thinker Isaac Newton’s quote, “If I have seen further it is by standing on the shoulders of Giants.” All these factors hence contribute significantly to an area of knowledge that, due to its methodology, is quite dependable. As a real-life scenario, in the issue of climate change, scientists have used inductive reasoning to conclude that the earth’s climate is changing through natural processes. The validity of this was then tested by applying deductive reasoning by specifically observing how the burning of fossil fuels accelerate the change in climate. Thus, the scientist can conclude that human (non-natural) activity is necessary to explain the current change in climate, since it cannot be explained merely by natural processes. Through this methodology, one can begin to understand a potential threat to mankind through the forecasting of results, illustrating how scientific knowledge touches upon issues and predicts those that are most grave and relevant to civilization while also suggesting solutions to them. It is thus justified that natural sciences can be regarded in a high esteem.

While there is good justification for regarding knowledge in the natural sciences highly, it may be prone to a lack of reliability – scientific methodology is sometimes susceptible to erroneous data and exploitation, thus possibly undermining its value. Mathematician Jacob Bronowski once said: “Science is a way of describing reality; it is therefore limited by the limits of observation, and it asserts nothing which is outside observation.” He implicitly points out the inevitability of ‘bad’ science potentially affecting society negatively. Particularly, scientists may manipulate the standard scientific process of drawing conclusions; some may deliberately create specious knowledge to seek financial gain or simply fame. Therefore, the ability to exploit the method in which one creates science implies that scientific knowledge sometimes cannot be regarded so highly. As a real-life example, pseudoscience can perhaps be seen as the Achilles’ heel of the natural sciences; it appears like actual science on its surface, but none of it is scientifically tested through inductive and deductive reasoning. Some elders in my own extended family, for instance, believe in astrology, because it is part of their popular culture. This attractiveness of pseudoscience permeates widespread belief, offering people, like some of my family, a flawed view of the world and ultimately an ignorance to the truth. However, my argument here is limited; pseudoscience technically is not true empirical science at heart. In the end, knowledge in the natural sciences is founded – just like what Bronowski stated – on the principle of observation, which is nevertheless more of a strength than a limitation.

            Regarding the area of knowledge of history, there is solid justification for viewing it as less highly that scientific knowledge, in that it is inherently uncertain and thus more unreliable. Literary critic Paul de Man articulated that “The bases for historical knowledge are not empirical facts but written texts, even if these texts masquerade in the guise of wars or revolutions.” The methodology in acquiring historical knowledge hence involves the historian identifying specific sources, like text, regarding historical events and then put them into context, linking events to create historical trend. However, what subsequently arises is the historian’s interpretation of a particular historical source that becomes exposed to their personal bias, implying disagreement between historians and in due course unreliability. This creates a difference in perspective, wherein it would seem that each historian has their own version of the past. On this justification, it is apparent that historical knowledge, because of its underlying doubt, cannot be regarded in a high esteem. There are several illustrations of historical uncertainty due to the actuality of contradicting perspectives, one for instance being the ambiguity over the true cause of the American Revolution. The typical textbook perspective asserts that the American Revolution was caused by several exploitative British impositions which eventually angered colonists, while many historians may argue that it was caused by events like as early as the French and Indian War. Therefore, the ambiguity and possible paradox that multiple perspectives provide in history make it harder for one to know a definite truth and have historical knowledge that is entirely objective. Rather, the subjectivity of history undermines its ‘high’ regard.

            However, there is some justification that historical knowledge can be regarded ‘highly’ if one were to consider how humans utilize it to learn from their past mistakes. Philosopher George Santayana’s once said that “Those who cannot remember the past are condemned to repeat it.” There is effectively no present without a past, and it is history that is the knowledge of the past. Santayana underscores how history allows one to understand the patterns of human civilization, and one can use this to their advantage when considering the future. As such, the pertinence of history in terms of human affairs gives it some value to bear in mind. As a real-life scenario, slavery is a historical topic from which humans have both benefited from and been degraded by. Through events like the American Civil War, people began to understand the unethical and dehumanizing nature of slavery, and so humans have naturally moved away from it. Humans have therefore learned from their past mistakes; it is most probable that slavery will not be practiced again because of the adversity it has caused. These standards and patterns that historical knowledge cultivate model humankind’s future, justifying why history may be highly regarded. Nevertheless, Santayana did also assert that “History is a pack of lies about events that never happened told by people who weren't there.” Thus, the inherent unreliability in history perhaps overshadows its value here.

            The question itself of whether there is solid justification to regard knowledge in the natural sciences more highly than that in history retains some weaknesses. The question would be better answered if the wordage “more highly” were to be communicated in a less ambiguous manner. The diction in “highly” connotates superiority, so the question assumes that one area of knowledge is perhaps ‘better’ than another. However, this is not an appropriate way to characterize an area of knowledge; evidently, the view of one area of knowledge being unassumingly superior to another is a subjective and controversial argument that will likely not have “solid justification.” Therefore, I have interpreted “more highly” to describe value in terms of the rigor of scientific knowledge compared to historical knowledge. This way, providing “good justification” for my argument – being in favor of knowledge in the natural sciences versus knowledge in history – would be more achievable.  

            Knowledge in the natural sciences is created through the direct observation of the world and is subsequently quite accurate. Dissimilarly, knowledge in history is created through one’s interpretation of a source from long ago and is as such frequently contentious. This is solid justification for the argument of regarding scientific knowledge “more highly” than historical knowledge. Nonetheless, while science may be seen as a more certain and overshadowing area of knowledge compared to history due to its reliable empirical methodology and vast applications, it has its cons – its methodology is limited and prone to misusage. This is the same case in history, in which the inevitability of countless perspectives on a historical issue due to a historian’s cognitive bias creates uncertainty. Thus, history is perhaps less approachable than science. Still, history allows us to see ourselves as before in order to shape who we are now and who we will be – it creates precedent that humans build off of. It is apparent that there is some justification for why history can be regarded more highly than science, but there is solid justification for why science can be regarded more highly than history.

 

Bibliography:

“Quote by Arthur M. Schlesinger Jr.” Goodreads, https://www.goodreads.com/quotes/1199803-science-and-technology-revolutionize-our-lives-but-memory-tradition-and.

Newton, Isaac. Received by Robert Hooke, England, 5 Feb. 1676, England.

Bronowski, Jacob. “Science is a way of describing reality; it is therefore limited by the limits of observation, and it asserts nothing which is outside observation.”

Man, Paul de. “Blindness and Insight: Essays in the Rhetoric of Contemporary Criticism.” Literary History and Literary Modernity, Oxford University Press, New York, NY, 1971, p. 165.

Santayana, George. “Reason in Common Sense.” The Life of Reason: The Phases of Human Progress, vol. 1, London Constable, 1906, p. 284. Internet Archive, https://archive.org/details/thelifeofreasono00santuoft/page/284/mode/2up.

“Quote by George Santayana.” Goodreads, https://www.goodreads.com/quotes/650898-history-is-a-pack-of-lies-about-events-that-never.

 

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

Why did the chicken cross the road?

Notable physicists answer….  Why did the chicken cross the road? Albert Einstein: The chicken did not cross the road. The road passed beneath the chicken. It’s relative. Erwin Schrodinger: A chicken? Why not a cat? Isaac Newton: Due to a net force acting upon the chicken. Carl Sagan: There are billions and billions of such chickens, crossing roads just like this one, all across the universe. Albert Michelson and Edward Morley: We could not detect the road. Our experiment was a failure. Werner Heisenberg: We can never know the momentum of the chicken if do know its position and vice versa. This question cannot be answered. Richard Feynman: What is the trajectory of the chicken? Charles Coulomb: A chicken on the other side of the road had the opposite charge of the chicken and the chicken was thus repelled to the chicken on the other side of the road. Galileo Galilei: Because the chicken put one foot in front of the other and a sufficient number of steps to

The effects of new knowledge

I have selected three objects/entities that I will use as evidence to answer the following question (courtesy of the International Baccalaureate Organization for creating this question for the Theory of Knowledge class). Can new knowledge change established values or beliefs? -  Object 1: Image of the cosmic microwave background radiation  This is an image of the cosmic microwave background radiation (CMBR), the electromagnetic radiation which is remnant from the earliest stage of the universe; the image has also been my go-to computer background. The CMBR’s discovery in 1965 effectively confirmed the Big Bang theory of the universe’s origins, which is why it interests me as someone who passions cosmology. However, before its discovery, it was the established belief both in the realm of science as well as in religion that the universe had been in existence for eternity. The Big Bang theory simply was not compatible with the beliefs of the larger portion of religious sects; for instance

"I am curious! Are you?" An Interpretation...

I have made a poem that reflects on the famous poem 'I'm Nobody! Who are you?' by Emily Dickinson into a completely different topic but still does follow the structure and idea: The poem by Emily Dickinson: I’m Nobody! Who are you? I'm Nobody! Who are you? Are you - Nobody - too? Then there's a pair of us! Don’t tell! they'd advertise - you know! How dreary - to be - Somebody! How public - like a Frog - To tell one's name - the livelong June - To an admiring Bog! My interpretation of the above: I am curious! Are you? I am Curious! Are you? Are you Curious too? A pair of us, there is! Dare tell a lad – and he’ll make an ad! How astounding – being – Curious. How open – like a monkey’s cries – To ask a question – until answered – To the Curious!